˟

Dictionary of the Bible

627

 
Image of page 0648

MIRACLES

whether in any cases this obscure psychic force was an unknown condition of His miracles is a matter of secondary importance.

(6) A second suggestion, made by the late Duke of Argyll (Reign of Law, p. 16), is that God chooses and uses laws unknown to man, or laws which, even it he knew, he could not use. He thinks that this would meet the prejudice of scientific thought against effects without causes. This explanation recognizes that miracles are not explicable by the laws of nature as known to man, and that it is of God's free choice that for certain ends He uses means otherwise unknown. As these laws are quite hypothetical, and as this use of them only occasionally is not at all probable, this explanation does not appear to make miracles any more credible.

(c) We may now attempt to define more closely what we mean by a miracle. It does seem, on the whole, desirable to restrict the term 'miracle' to an external event of which there is sensible evidence. Inward changes, such as in the prophetic inspiration, or the religious conversion of an individual, however manifest the Divine presence and action may be for the person having the experience, should not be described as miracles, unless with some qualification such as spiritual or moral. The negative feature of the external event which justifies our describing it as a miracle is that it is inexpUcable by the natural forces and laws as known to us. The will of man is a force in nature with which we are familiar, and therefore the move-ments of the body under the control of the will are not to be described as miraculous. We say more than we are justified in saying if we describe a miracle as an interference with the laws and forces of nature, or a breach in the order of nature; for just zs the physical forces and laws allow the exercise of human will in the movements of the body, so the power that produces the miracle may, nay must, be conceived as so closely related to nature that its exercise results in no disturbance or disorder in nature. The miracle need not interfere with the continuity of nature at all. The modem theory of Evolution is not less, but more, favourable to the belief in miracle. It is not a finished machine, but a growing organism, that the world appears. Life transcends, and yet combines and controls physical forces (Lodge's lAt^ and Matter, p. 198). Mind is not explicable by the brain, and yet the will directs the movements of the body. There is a creative action of God in the stages of the evolution, which attaches itself to the conserving activity. Applying the argu-ment from analogy, we may regard the Person of Christ and the miracles that cluster round His Person as such a creative action of God. If we adequately estimate the significance of the Exodus in the history of mankind, the providential events connected with it will assume greater credibility. But there is a final consideration. The purpose of God in Christ is not only perfective the completion of the world 's evolution ; it is also redemp-tive the correction of the evil sin had brought on the human race. It was fitting that the redemption of man from sin should be acco-npanied by outward remedial signs, the relief of his need and removal of his sufferings. God is without variation and shadow that is cast by turning in His purpose, but His action is conditioned, and must necessarily be conditioned, by the results of man's use of the freedom which for His wise and holy ends He bestowed. He may in His action transcend His normal activity by a more direct manifestation of Himself than the natural processes of the world afford. The consistency of character of a human personality is not disproved by an excep-tional act when a crisis arises; and so, to deal effectively with sin for man's salvation, God may use miracles as means to His ends without any break in the con-tinuity of His wisdom, righteousness, and grace.

4. Objections. It seemed desirable to state the facts.

MIRACLES

the proofs for them, and the reasonableness of them, before taking up the objections that are made. These objections refer to two points, the possibility of miracle at all, and the sufficiency of the evidence for the miracles of the Bible. Each of these may be very briefly dealt with, (o) For materialism, which recognizes only physical forces; and pantheism, which so identifies God and man that the order of nature is fixed by the necessity of the nature of God ; and even for deism, which confines the direct Divine activity to the beginning, and excludes it from the course of the world, miracles are impossible. Agnosticism, which regards the ultimate reality as an inscrutable mystery, is under no logical compulsion to deny the possibility of miracles; Huxley, for instance, pronounces such denial unjustifiable. Two reasons against the possibiUty of miracles may be advanced from a theistic standpoint. In the interests of science it may be maintained that the uniformily of ncUure ex-cludes miracle; but, as has just been shown, the theory of Evolution has so modified the conception of uni-formity that tills argument has lost its force. Life and mind, when first appearing in the process of evolution, were breaches in the uniformity. The uniformity of nature is consistent with fresh stages of development, inexplicable by their antecedents; and only when science has resolved life and mind into matter 'wiU the argument regain any validity. In the interests of philosophy, it may be argued that miracles interrupt the continuity of thought: the world as it is is so reasonable (idealism) or so good (optimism) that any change is unthinkable. But the affirmation ignores many of the problems the world as it is presents: sin, sorrow, death are real ; would not the solution of these problems give both a more reasonable and a better world? and if miracles should be necessary to such a solution, they are thinkable. Again, is it not somewhat arrogant to make man's estimate of what is reasonable and good the measure of God's wisdom and grace?

(6) The more usual objection is the insufftctencu of the evidence. Hume laid down this criterion: 'No testi-mony is sufficient to establish a miracle unless the testimony be of such a kind that its falsehood would be more miraculous than the fact which it endeavours to estabUsh. Or briefly, it is contrary to experience that a miracle should be true, but not contrary to experience that testimony should be false.' But to this statement it may properly be objected, that it assumes what is to be proved ; for, while it may be contrary to ordinary experience that miracles happen, what the defenders of miracles maintain is that there have been exceptional experiences of miracles. If miracles were common, they would cease to be so described; their uncommon-ness does not prove their incredibiUty. Although the test is one that has no warrant, yet it may be argued that Christ's character and resurrection would stand it. It is less credible that the portrait of Jesus given in the Gospels was invented, than that Jesus lived as there depicted. It is less credible that the Apostolic faith in the risen Lord, and all it accomplished, should have its origin in illusion, than that He rose from the dead. The improbability of miracle is usually the tacit assump-tion when the sufficiency of the evidence is denied. If the relation of God to the world is conceived as a constant, immanent, progressive, perfective, redemptive activity, the probabiUty of miracles will be so great that the evidence sufficient to prove an ordinary event will be regarded as satisfactory, provided always that this test is met, that the miracle is connected with the fulfilment of the Divine purpose, and is congruous in its character with the wisdom, righteousness, and grace of God.

5. Value.— A few words may in conclusion be added regarding the value of the miracles. The old apologetic view of miracles as the credentials of the doctrines of Christianity is altogether discredited. It is the truth of the doctrines that makes the fact of the miracles

623